Abstracts of the meeting in Estonia (Tartu – Puhtu
–Tallinn, June 14–17, 2002)
Edited by
Kaie Kotov
Kalevi Kull
Tartu — University of Tartu
2002
"The process of message exchanges, or semiosis, is an indispensable characteristic of all terrestrial life forms. It is this capacity for containing, replicating, and expressing messages, of extracting their signification, that, in fact, distinguishes them more from the nonliving - except for human agents, such as computers or robots, that can be programmed to simulate communication - than any other traits often cited. The study of the twin processes of communication and signification can be regarded as ultimately a branch of the life science, or as belonging in large part to nature, in some part to culture, which is, of course, also a part of nature" (Sebeok 1991: 22).
This meeting represents a step in our joint effort to understand living beings as sign systems. The Gathering in Tartu also means that the annual worldwide conferences on biosemiotics have turned into a reality. After a very successful first Gathering in Copenhagen — in May 24–27, 2001 — the current meeting is going to develop the ideas of semiotic biology.
In order to maintain the international network, the current abstracts volume includes both the abstracts of the papers presented at the meeting, and several contributions by the authors who attend it in an epistolary way.
The meeting has been organised by the Department of Semiotics of the University of Tartu, Jakob von Uexküll Centre, Tallinn Zoo, and the Biosemiotics Group of the University of Copenhagen.
References
Emmeche,
Claus 2001. The emergence of signs of living feelings: Reverberations from the
first Gatherings in Biosemiotics. Sign Systems Studies 29(1): 369–376.
Sebeok, T. A. 1991. A
Sign is Just a Sign. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Myrdene Anderson
Department of Sociology and Anthropology
Purdue University
West Lafayette, IN 47907-1365 USA
E-mail: myanders@ecn.purdue.edu
A notion once applied, descriptively, to the retention of embryological characters from an antecedent form of an organism, into a subsequent, more mature period in the ontogeny of a phylogenetic descendent form — neoteny is now appreciated as a fundamental systems process concomitant with hierarchization. Specifically, neoteny connects to constituent simplification, codependence, flexibility, and exogenous dissipative structures, while hierarchization connects with the overarching, maturing coevolutionary system with its absorption of noise, tolerances permitting resilience, and endogenous dissipative structures. Consequently, the domain of neoteny crosscuts, and even articulates, biology, culture, and behavior.
An understanding of the dynamics of neoteny in systemic evolution and in interspecific relations leads to fresh insight with respect to domestication, or, more properly, codomestication. Rather than reduce domestication to human activity through artificial selection (selection-in), with or without intention, the topic must enlarge to acknowledge the shape of ontogenetic trajectories and the serendipity in the integration of enabling (largely informational, in ontogenesis) and limiting (largely energetic, in ‘natural’ selection-out) constraints.
Codomesticates exhibit many neotenous traits and processes, some pre-dating the domestication process, some consequent to it, and most intensified by it. Humans, as codomesticates, are further neotenized and domesticated by culture. Such an approach to codomestication sheds light on other interspecific relations, including protection, predation, and parasitism. The analytically distinctive properties of codomestication involve a complex of cooperation and competition, consisting largely in loops of information throughput in patently open, disequilibrious systems, while intentional protection within or without a domestication framework involves an asymmetric investment of energy in more closed, equilibrious systems.
Predation involves a competitive tradeoff of predominately energy accruing to successful predator and of predominatelly information accruing to the surviving prey. The ultimate potential in reciprocal cooperation lies in host-parasite relations. The codomestication process, often emerges from predation and/or protection scenarios, as outlined here, and not infrequently merges with a category of host-parasite relations best glossed as coparasitic. These dynamics of the recursive process of neoteny underlie the prehistory and history of codomestication, as well as provide some algorithm for contemporary trends, with or without deliberate human intervention.
Stefan Artmann
Institute of Philosophy
Friedrich-Schiller-University
Zwätzengasse 9, 07740 Jena, Germany
stefan.artmann@uni-jena.de
The French molecular biologist François Jacob has outlined a theory of biologic evolution as tinkering. From a methodologic point of view, his approach can be seen as a biologically specified version of the abstract relation between laws, describing the dynamics of a system, and boundary conditions on this dynamics. Evolutionary theory, then, would finally be a theory of consistent biologic histories, i.e., of coherent transformations of contingent boundary conditions due to reduplication, recombination, mutation, and hierarchization of a limited set of given structures, so that the same or very similar structures fulfil several functions in different contexts. Because every proposal of some evolutionary causality has to fit in with this general scheme, Jacob’s theory of tinkering is a meta-theory sketching a framework for analysing the form of evolution. In semiotic perspective, tinkering is a pragmatic concept well-known from the information-theoretic anthropology of Claude Lévi-Strauss. In idealized contrast to an engineer, the tinkerer has to accept the concrete contingent restrictions of his material resources as only gradually changeable constraints on his well-thought-out projects. Jacobian biopragmatics examines evolution as a biologic analogue to this human tinkering but obviously devoid of any projecting subjectivity. To validate this analogy, four basic principles of Jacobian biopragmatics concerning its main aspects are proposed. Firstly, the fundamental notion of biopragmatics is context-dependency: every biologic information can act as information only in relation to a context. Secondly, the main interest of biopragmatics is to explore the potentials the evolutionary process possesses (especially in respect to genetic engineering as a scientifically refined form of tinkering). Thirdly, the research strategy of the biopragmatician is characterized by the non-existence of an essential methodic difference between object- and meta-level: he has to follow in his research the same logic of tinkering as his object in its evolutionary generation. Fourthly, biopragmatics is connected to semantics by the theory of narrative programs, and to syntax by the notion of logical depth.
Marcello Barbieri
Department of Morphology and Embryology, University of Ferrara
Via Fossato di Mortara 64, 44100 Ferrara, Italy
brr@unife.it
Coding characteristics have been discovered
not only in protein synthesis but in various other natural processes, thus
showing that the genetic code is not an isolated case in the organic
world. Other examples are the sequence codes, the adhesion code,
the signal transduction codes, the splicing codes, the sugar
code, the histone code, and probably more. These discoveries however have not had a significant impact because of
the widespread belief that organic codes are not real but metaphorical
entities. They are supposed to lack arbitrariness and codemakers, the two
qualifying features of real codes. Here it is shown that the arbitrariness
issue can be solved on an experimental basis, while the codemaker issue is
dependent on our theoretical description of the cell and can only be solved by a
new concept. In order to appreciate the reality of the organic codes, in short,
it is necessary to have not only a more critical evaluation of the experimental
data but also a new theory of the living system.
Mette Böll
Institute of Molecular Biology
The Biosemiotic Group
University of Copenhagen
Sølvgade 83, DK 1307 København K, Denmark
metteboell@get2net.dk
The social play behavior of animals is poorly understood in terms of traditional biological explanations. There are no exact definitions of these types of behavior, and there is no ethological method that applies to the behavioral category of play. By focusing on the intersubjective field between the playing individuals — instead of on the individual as an entity — I try to create space for a new approach to ethology. This approach involves a biosemiotic view on the “socio-empathic field”. When animals play they learn to negotiate and define themselves clearly in the social group, this demands empathic understanding. Since play is found throughout the animal world, there must be evolutionary capacities underlying this type of construction in the social system.
Søren Brier
KVL, IØSL, Copenhagen, Denmark
sbr@kvl.dk
In 1995, John Brockman wrote a book called The Third Culture. The book was based on interviews with prominent scientists like Stephen Jay Gould, Lynn Margulis, Marvin Minsky, Murrau-Gell-Mann, and Francisco Varela. The title was inspired by Snow’s book from 1959: The Two Cultures: the culture of science and technology and the culture of the humanities (the intellectual scholars). In an addition to the second edition of his book (1963) Snow talks about the necessity of a third culture to bridge the gab between the other two and make a new synergy. Brockman points out that the third culture he describes is not exactly that of Snow’s. What is happening is that a handful of researchers within science and technology have started writing books for the broader public about the philosophical consequences of the new evolutionary worldview of complexity and self-organization. This is based on new discoveries in science and technology, especially computing. The discoveries seem to affect the understanding of the deeper meaning of life in the universe. The new sciences of complexity within mathematics, physics, and chemistry are through the concept of information making contact with biology and the ideas of self-organization, agency and autopoiesis developed there. An informational-evolutionary self-organizing worldview for both the universe and the living systems in a complex mutual interdependency is the result.
Although researchers, scholars and popularisators, like Allan Guth, Paul Davis, Lee Smolin, David Dennett, Stuart Kauffman, have all contributed to this new view of the world as a self-organising complexity with no clearly determined lawful foundation, they have not yet dared to address the concepts of meaning and signification. These are concepts usually attached to continental philosophy such as structuralism, semiology, phenomenology and hermeneutics.
Peircian semiotics, and especially its biosemiotic version, is unusual in its integration of qualia, signification and semiosis across “dead” and living nature, culture and machines Connecting to ethology through Uexküll’s Umwelt concept, biosemiotics regards the sphere of signification, created by every living system as the primary living space. Thus the habitat in the ecological niche becomes a meaningful sphere.
Through embodied cognitive semantics as for instance that of
Lakoff and Johnson’s, the influence of embodiment on the construction of
cultural meaning through language is revealed.
Through endosemiotics the production of meaning is carried inside the
organisms to the communication between the cells, and in microsemiotics even
within the cells. In the development of physiosemiotics (J. Deely), the
production of meaning is taken into “dead” nature and the development of the
universe, in accordance with Peirce’s philosophy of hylozoism, synechism and
agapism. Biosemiotics is introducing the concept of meaning to science, thus
paving the way for a true Third Culture. Recent work by Andreas Weber develops
further aspects of such an understanding.
Luis Emilio Bruni
Institute of Molecular Biology
The Biosemiotics Group
University of Copenhagen
Sølvgade 83, DK 1307 København K
bruni@mermaid.molbio.ku.dk
In the extensive reconceptualization of the nature and organisation of genome architectures that has taken place at the turning of the XX century, the communication potential between genomes has become of the highest importance. The entire set of genomes of all living organisms has been defined elsewhere as the “genome space”. Just as we are bound to bear in mind that all live manifestations are historical entities we have to keep in mind also that all living entities are alive at the same moment. So the “global genome space” is a dynamic space that contains (and continuously renovates) the potentiality of the “global phenotype”. But unless we want to remain stuck to a geno-centric view, we have to consider the mutual semiotic constitutivity of the global genome and its phenotypical counterpart. Genomes do not walk around by themselves.
The potentiality for “change” and for the production of novelty implicit in the genome space may be regulated by the actual manifestation of such potentiality in relation to the actual environmental conditions. It is suggested that the constant digital-analogical-digital translation, from global genome to global phenotype and vice versa can be considered as a homeostatic system of mutual determination (and change). This process is mediated by codes which are formed at different hierarchical levels out of an indeterminate number of dyadic causal relations, specific “lock and key” interactions, that by their simultaneous occurrence create a context that gives rise to emergent and “de-emergent” triadic relations.
Is it ever possible to separate the hen from the egg?
Sergei
V. Chebanov
St. Petersburg League of
Scientists
31 Moika, Apt. 12, St. Petersburg 191186, Russia
chebanov@sc2747.spb.edu
chebanov@iephb.nw.ru
In my previous work in which I proved the necessities
of creation of bilateralist biosemiotics, I focused my attention on the nature
of biological sense. The arising problems are most evident in an example of
semantics triplets, in particular, in discussing the mechanisms of
correspondence between the adapter and acceptor in t-RNA.
Certainly, any component connected with the t-RNA is
present at any biological semantics. However, to reduce all biological
semantics to semantics t-RNA would be reductionism, but further, from the
practical point of view, such an arrangement lacks perspective.
At the present time there are at least two another ways
of introducing biological semantics.
The first of which -
consideration of sequences nucleotides DNA/RNA and sequences amino-acids in
peptides from the perspective of their functional synonym/homonym. Thus, three
moments are of most importance:
— The transformation from sense to meaning.
— Opens up the
way to restriction by unilateralistic concepts of semiotic means or simply
cybernetics.
— Appears the
opportunity of using philological-linguistic data about graphic poetry features
(palindromes, heterograms, acrostics), which at present time do not appear as
marginal phenomenons of language.
Second - reference to sense in ethological semiotics.
The main problem thus is overcoming anthropomorphism. In this context two
interconnected areas are especially interesting:
— Reconstructing
taxon-specific umwelten in a J. von Uexküll’s sense. However, this umwelt is
not a semiotic environment, but special material of the plan du contenu
for generation taxon-specific semiotic means.
— Revealing
taxo-specific invariants of receptions (in the Pribram-Galanter-Glaser sense),
which, on the one hand, exist as components of morpho-functional organization
of a body of a living being, and as another — as “building material” of this
umwelt.
John Collier
Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research
Adolf Lorenz Gasse 2, A-3422 Altenberg, Austria
john.collier@kla.univie.ac.at
Information carrying capacity is the consequence of a system having certain causal (dynamical) properties. These properties can be defined at a single scalar level, allowing but not implying arbitrarily high degrees of specifiability. The expression of information, however, requires at least a second dynamically defined level. This is sufficient for at least a form of protoreference, but, I will argue, not a real pragmatics, and hence not a real semantics.
Yagmur Denizhan, Candas Sert
Electronics and Electrical Engineering Department
Bogazici University
PO Box 2, 80815 Bebek-Istanbul,Turkey
denizhan@boun.edu.tr
Characterised by positive feedback, metasystem transitions appear to play a fundamental role as the quanta of evolution in natural history. In addition to that, semiotic processes are of prime importance for the realisation of those metasystem transitions. From a thermodynamic point of view, the emergence of more complex, self-producing agents that tend to become “greedier” consumers of energy gradients, depends on the emergence of more advanced forms of semiosis. The possible efficiency improvement in the energy consumption achieved through semiotic means can shift the balance between the advantages (such as the increased access to energy resources) and the disadvantages (such as the increased amount of the so-called “tax” paid in the form of entropy production) of greediness in the positive direction. As an evolutionary consequence, more symbolic forms of semiosis that allow higher competence for abstraction, anticipation and efficiency emerge. In this semiotic and thermodynamic context, the relevance of the concept of senescence will also be discussed.
Klaus Emmeche
Department of Biological Chemistry
University of Copenhagen
Sølvgade 83, DK 1307 Copenhagen K, Denmark
emmeche@nbi.dk
The evolutionary emergence of biosystems with inner, qualitative states have not been explained in any sufficient way within the traditional neo-Darwinian paradigm. Here, natural selection would appear to work just as well on insentient zombies with the right behavioral input-output relations as their fellow beings, the real sentient animals. In consciousness studies, one talks about the ‘hard’ problem of qualia. Is it possible to describe a set of principles about sign action, causality and emergent evolution, drawn from biosemiotics and complex systems research, that will allow us to sketch a theory of the emergence of conscious experiences in evolution? An attempt is made to give such a list of principles, and “the hard problem” will be reformulated as the problem of relating experimental biology to experiential biology.
Donald Favareau
Department of Applied Linguistics
University of California
3300 Rolfe Hall, Los Angeles, California 90095-1531, USA
favareau@ucla.edu
In a radical departure from both the formal and the materialist reductionism so often prevalent in the disciplines of linguistics, sociology, anthropology and neuroscience, a growing number of researchers at the interdisciplinary interface known as ethnography of Communication have, over the course of the last three decades, compiled compelling evidence demonstrating that “language” as it is actually realized in naturally occurring, everyday talk-in-interaction, derives its semiotic efficacy more from the active co-participation of situated speakers in creating contexts of relevancy, constraint and possibility for each other’s actions than from the mental, computational recombination of referential tokens within the bounds of some predetermined, category-structuring syntax.
Rigorously empirical and devoted to an explication of how language-using agents themselves display to each other their understandings of what they are doing as they are collaboratively making meaning (as opposed to how theoreticians of such meaning-making may interpret those displays analytically), the nascent disciplines of ethnography of communication and conversation analysis are, in much the same fashion as the nascent discipline of biosemiotics, studying “meaning” as an ongoing interactional achievement among linked and living agents — a caused and causative event in the world, rather than a determined and determining referent or thing.
Understanding the world of conversational interaction to be one wherein the actions of its participants mutually and reciprocally co-create the conditions for each other to realize singular actualities out of the realm of possibilities created by those actions (and wherein those actualities subsequently constitute the conditions for further possibility), conversation analysis and ethnography of communication studies share with the semiotic philosophy of Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) the notion of a perpetually built environment of meaning that is irreducibly relational and interactionally accomplished and sustained.
The focus of this talk will be an introduction to some of the basic principles, methodologies and research data of conversation analysis, and an attempt to situate such research and its findings within the broader study of meaning-making among living agents that is the goal of biosemiotics. I will argue that the former can well illuminate and assist the latter in its continuing effort to understand the principles whereby not only our social worlds, but our very biological world itself comes into being not as a “given” in the furniture of the universe, but as a fundamentally interactional, locally organized, massively co-constructed, context-sensitive and context-creating, ongoing semiotic achievement in that universe instead.
Sune Frølund
Institute for Educational Philosophy
The Danish University of Education
Emdrupvej 101 DK-2400 Copenhagen NV
Denmark
surf@dpu.dk
Biosemiotics
claims the sign to be the fundamental biological unit. The ontological status
of the sign, however, is ambiguous. Are signs simply ‘there’ or are they only
existing for the interpreter? If a sign is defined ‘a difference that makes a
difference’, it is still unsettled if a sign is an agent itself or the tool of
an agent. Or if the receiver — through an interpretational ‘act’ — is the true
origin of any signification.
Biosemiotics seems to claim,
that all meaning is the result of signification, of a sign-making. The
reason for this is probably, that it makes the sign a good match to the
efficient ‘cause’ of physics, thus saving the explanatory force of traditional
science. On the other hand biosemiotics tacitly assumes, that signs not only
‘make’ sense in a quasi-causal way, but also ‘have’ a meaning in the good
old-fashioned way. If not, the carefree mixture of traditional naturalism and
antropomorfism (a stylistic free riding-trait of biosemiotics) will collapse.
One could say, that
biosemiotics has taken a stand between Kant and Schelling. The kantian approach
(also seen in Jakob von Uexküll) traces all signification back to a
(quasi-human) subject , thus only allowing its ‘as-if’-status in external
nature. The schellingian approach (Schellings Naturphilosophie after
year 1801) insists on seeing humans, subjectivity, consciousness and meaning as
natural, thus having to extend the concepts of nature and matter in order to
avoid semiotic irrealism.
In Hans Jonas’ philosophy of
life the influence from Schelling is indisputable. Jonas attempts to
rehabilitate natural teleology and he develops a ‘cosmogonical’ or even
“speculative” concept of matter in order to save both the dynamic unity of
nature and the reality of meaning.
In its basic features the
Naturphilosophie and cosmology of Hans Jonas is not unlike the philosophy of
another Schelling-successor, Charles Sanders Peirce. To me it seems
indispensable for biosemiotics to elaborate more consequently into its
fundamentals to get a less ambiguous concept of sign and information. Even at
the cost of traditional physicalism and scientivism. My paper will contribute
to this aim through the philosophy of Hans Jonas.
Jesper Hoffmeyer
Department of Biological Chemistry
University of Copenhagen
Sølvgade 83, DK 1307 Copenhagen K, Denmark
hoffmeyer@mermaid.molbio.ku.dk
The finding, reported in the newspapers all over the world at February 11, 2001, that the human genome, previously believed to contain approximately 100,000 genes, did in fact only contain some thirty thousands genes has seriously challenged the received understanding of phenotypic determination. Perhaps as little as 300 genes separate the human species from that of the mouse. Thus, contrary to what we were often told, at least there cannot be a mutated gene for every item on the list of human sins. An analysis of gene action in Caenorhabditis elegans and in the virtual species Scitoi mesoib shows us how this can be.
Wolfgang Hofkirchner
Computer Science Department, HCI group
Institute of Design and Technology Assessment
Vienna University of Technology
Favoritenstrasse 9, A-1040 Vienna, Austria
hofi@igw.tuwien.ac.at
The paper will deal with the differentia specifica of information and sign processes in biotic systems in the framework of a Unified Theory of Information.
Starting point will be the co-extension of semiosis and self-organization. On the one hand, semiosis and self-organization in biotic systems has to be distinguished from semiosis and self-organization in physical and chemical systems. On the other, it has to be distinguished from that in human systems. The paper will discuss some approaches to giving the essence of life and will focus on semiotic implications. It will conclude that the characteristics of the living in the perspective of a theory of evolutionary systems will serve as a novel function that has emerged in the course of the evolution of self-organizing systems and that the semiosic features of biotic systems in cognitive, communicative and co-operative respects derive from this very function.
Sungchul Ji
Department of Pharmacology and Toxicology, Ernest Mario School
of Pharmacy
Rutgers University, Piscataway, N.J. 08855, USA
sji@eohsi.rutgers.edu
Most, if not all, contemporary molecular and cell biologists seem to be working under the tacit assumption that the principles of physics and chemistry are necessary and sufficient to account for the observable properties of the living cell. Although this so-called ‘PC paradigm’ (P = physics; C = chemistry) has been enormously successful in the past century in unraveling the material details of the living cell, a growing number of biomedical scientists, since toward the end of the last century, has expressed the alternative view that physics and chemistry are necessary but may not be sufficient to account for life on the molecular and cellular levels. One such emerging perspective is the ‘PCL paradigm’ (L = linguistics) that began to be formulated in the late 1960’s (e.g., Pattee 1968; Marcus 1974), according to which, in addition to the laws and principles of physics and chemistry, those of linguistics are absolutely needed to completely account for life on the cellular and molecular levels (for a review, see Ji 2001). The conceptualization of the PCL paradigm was spurred by the surprising finding that the molecular language used by cells has design principles that are very similar to, or isomorphic with, those of human language (Ji 1997). Since linguistics is a major subdiscipline of semiotics, the PCL paradigm can be alternatively referred to as the ‘molecular semiotics’ or ‘microsemiotics’ paradigm (Ji 1999).
Theoretical and experimental evidences that have accumulated during the past three decades indicate that the living cell is a complementary union of two irreconcilably opposite aspects – the energy/matter aspect and the information aspect (Ji 2002). The conformon (i.e., sequence-specific conformational strains of biopolymers driving molecular work processes in the cell) theory embodies primarily the energy/matter aspect of the cell (Ji 2000; also in Ji 1991), while the cell language theory reflects the information aspect (Ji 1997). It has been found that the combination of the conformon and cell language theories provides more complete and coherent explanations, than any existing biological theories, for various molecular structures and processes in the cell, including the actions of molecular motors and pumps, oxidative phosphorylation, signal transduction, and the phenomenon of genome-wide coordinated gene expression revealed by the DNA microarray technique.
Ji, S. (ed.) 1991. Molecular
Theories of Cell Life and Death. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press,
1–237.
Ji, S. 1997. BioSystems
44: 17–39.
—1999. N. Y. Acad. Sci.
870: 411–417.
— 2000. BioSystems
54: 107–130.
— 2001. Semiotica, in
press.
— 2002. Fundamenta
Informaticae 49: 147–165.
Pattee, H. 1968. In: C. H.
Waddington (ed.), Towards a Theoretical Biology 1. Chicago: Aldine
Publishing Company, 67–93.
Marcus, S. 1974. Cahiers de
linguistique theorique et appliquee 11: 77–104.
Elisabeth Johansson
Department of Water and Environmental Studies
Linköping University,
S-581 83 Linköping, Sweden
elijo@tema.liu.se
During the last decade interest in both carbon and nitrogen dynamics has increased because of the predicted anthropogenically induced global changes in them, and the global climate change that may follow. Today, the understanding of carbon and nitrogen dynamics are mainly based on mechanical models that describe physico-chemical interactions related to these processes.
As a contribution towards our understanding of carbon and nitrogen dynamics I present my study on the exchange of methane and nitrous oxide fluxes with the atmosphere from a constructed wetland. In these studies I suggest that it is important to include biosemiotic perspectives in the gas flux models.
Thus, the aim of this study is to develop new paths for gas flux investigations in research fields related to constructed wetlands.
Kalevi Kull
Department of Semiotics, University of Tartu
Tiigi St. 78, Tartu, Estonia
kalevi@zbi.ee
(1) The phenomenon of biosemiosis, as well as semiosis in general, includes features that may be inaccessible via a methodology of a standard physical science; this requires an approach of semiotic science.
(2) There
exists a semiosic force — the force that appears as a result of communication
or a dialogue, an individual
connectedness via a signification or a dialogue sensu lato.
(3) A principal feature of the semiosic force is anticipation. As related to the concept of need, it distinguishes semiosis from non-semiosis.
(4) A search for other, as a general and universal feature or tendency of all active behaviour of organisms, provides a principle that bridges many problems of biosemiotics and ecosemiotics. One can see in the search for other (or in a ‘need for impression’, according to a zoosemiotic formulation by A. Turovski) a characteristics (or working principle) that is responsible simultaneously both for the fixation and for the evolving of codes.
(5) Biological evolution is a semiosic search.
Kull,
Kalevi 1999. Biosemiotics in the twentieth century: a view from biology. Semiotica
127(1/4): 385-414.
—
2000a. Active
motion, communicative aggregations, and the spatial closure of Umwelt. Annals of the New York
Academy of Sciences 901: 272–279
—
2000b. Trends in theoretical biology: the 20th century. Aquinas 43(2):
235–249.
—
2000c. Organisms can be proud to have been their own designers. Cybernetics
and Human Knowing 7(1): 45–55.
Turovski, Aleksei 2000. The
semiotics of animal freedom: A zoologist’s attempt to perceive the semiotic aim
of H. Hediger. Sign Systems Studies
28: 380–386.
Dominique Lestel
Department of cognitive science
Ecole normale supérieure
45, rue d’Ulm, 75005 Paris, France
Dominique.Lestel@ens.fr
Gregory Bateson thought that the great difference between human language and animal communications was in the fact that these later were unable to express negation. Even if we don’t agree about the rapidity of such a statement and its generality, it is nevertheless true that it leads to a very interesting question about the expression of negation among animals: are they able to do it, and how? In that paper, I wish to discuss Bateson’s statement from the point of view of contemporary researches in ethology and comparative psychology — in particular in play, sharing and regulation of power. I wish to show that if it is not possible to say that animals are not able to express negation, it does not mean that they are ble to express it as humans do. I will also show that interactions with humans lead animals to acquire new means to express negation. Finally, I shall discuss that question in the more general framework of a phylogenesis of meaning.
Andres Luure
Department of Semiotics
University of Tartu
Tiigi St. 78, 50140 Tartu, Estonia
luure@ut.ee
A distinction will be
introduced between relations (Verhältnisse) und relationships (Beziehungen).
The related are in relations, whereas relationships are made by the related.
Signs are connecting links
between relations and relationships.
A new perspective on sign
types will be suggested on the basis of a distinction between relations (Verhältnisse)
and relationships (Beziehungen).
If opposites are entirely
independent from each other and entirely separated then they coincide. In this
case they are in a relation. They are formed by this relation, i.e, they are
possible due to this relation.
If
opposites depend on each other by their interaction and immediate contact then
they exclude each other. In this case they are entering a relationship. This
relationship is made by them, i.e., it is actual due to them.
Signs are connecting links
between relations and relationships. Human reality (the reality as accessible
to human beings) has a sign character which in our experience is broken into
being formed by something objective and being made by someone subjective. We
are in an objective relation, and we are entering a subjective relationship.
Signs have been made by and from non-signs along with the human, and signs are
forming the entire world into signs.
Our life is experienced as
communication between object and subject. It seems that, on the basis of a
model of the object as the sender and and the subject as the addressee, Peirce
reduces the object to the "object" and the subject to the
"interpretant". In my interpretation of the Peircian terms, actually,
the object is what is forming and what is formed, whereas the interpretant is
what is made and what is making.
The object is a relation,
whereas the interpretant is a relationship. The sign is a relationship being in
a relation with an object, and a relation entering a relationship with an
interpretant. The sign is a connection between the object and the intepretant,
between the relation and the relationship. It combines both the relation
character and the relationship character.
The way a sign mediates
between the relation and the relationship (the object and the interpretant) may
be different. To denote these different ways I shall use the terms of Sebeok’s
sign typology in a reinterpreted manner:
left right
third level 5. symbol 6. name
second level 3. icon 4. index
first level 1. signal 2. symptom
In the left
column, we deal with objects (relations), whereas in the right column, we deal
with interpretants (relationships). An object-sign is formed by an
interpretant, whereas an interpretant-sign makes an interpretant.
Now I will expound the sign
types in the context of Peirce's metaphysic and biosemiotics. In the terms of
our table, the first level, the second level and the third level correspond to
Peirce's Firstness, Secondness and Thirdness. Peirce concentrates on our right
column, i.e., on how the interpretant gets made.
On the first level, the
object-sign is a "signal", whereas the interpretant-sign is a
"symptom". A signal is an object in itself, revealing itself only
symptomatically. A symptom is a symptom (a sensuous appearance) of a signal. In
Peirce's terms, chance-spontaneity is signal, and feeling is symptom.
Signal is sign without
system: it does not depend on any sign system. It determines itself by itself,
being an interpretant forming itself and relation identical to its related.
Symptom is context without text. It determines itself by itself, being a sign
making itself and a related identical to its relationship.
The second level is the
properly semiotic level and the properly biosemiotic level. "Icons"
are signs in a sign system and "indices" are texts on the background
of a context. The signs are formed by the sign system and the texts are made by
the context. An icon is like a sign in Uexküll's terms (in anthroposemiotics -
like a language sign in Saussure's terms) and an index is like an adaptation
sign or adaptation text (which has not yet been elaborated in biosemiotics) or,
in anthroposemiotics, a speech text (a message).
To understand an icon, let
us regard Saussure’s language sign. Saussure distinguishes between the
signifier, the signified and the sign. In my interpretation, the sign is the
interpretant, the signified is the object and the signifier is the sign
(representamen). The interpretant is the relation forming the object
(signified) and the sign (signifier). The interpretant is formed by the sign
system. The relation (sign) is a relation of a relation (signified) and a
relationship (signifier). Here, the sign is the same as the signified. The same
relation is both the interpretant (sign) and the object (signified). So an icon
is a relation being a relation of itself and a relationship. In biosemiotics,
for instance, to each function of an organism there corresponds an icon, and to
its system of functions there corresponds a sign system. (In icons, the sign
and the object are similar to each other by being each others "reverse
sides".) In Peirce's metaphysic, the "icons" are habits or laws.
The counterparts of the
"indices" in Peirce's metaphysic are the reaction senses. The subject
is free in its resistance to the object. The interpretant is the subject such
as it changes into in the context of the object's presence. The sign (text) is
the subject such as it "reacts" to the object's presence. The sign
and the interpretant are states of the same substance (the subject). The object
just is the object's presence. In biosemiotics, the subject of adaptation is
changing from the sign into the interpretant. This process of change is its
adaptation in the context of the object. The index (text) is the relationship
between itself (the relationship) and the relation (the object). As the sign,
the text is what the object is in the relationship with, and as the
interpretant, the text is the very relationship. (The "indices" are
texts gathering information about the object in the course of their
self-interpretation.)
On the third level, we deal
with "symbols" and "names". A symbol is a system without
signs. A name is a text without context. The symbol is what forms the
possibility of signs. The name is what makes the actuality of text. The symbol
is the initial (true) object. The name is the final (true) interpretant.
The symbol is the relation
(interpretant) of the relation (interpretant) with itself (sign). In the
symbol, all relationships have been "turned" into relations. Signs
(and especially, symbols in Peirce's sense) are finite projections of the
initial symbol. The symbol is the source of all possible signs. In the symbol
in itself, everything means everything. In Peirce's metaphysic, the
"symbol's" counterpart seems to be God.
The name is a relationship
being in a relation with the relation (the symbol). The name does not mean
anything beyond itself, it is the end of interpretation. Nevertheless, the
Named is embodied in the Name. The name is the sign, the unreachable end of the
name is the interpretant, and what is embodied in the name is the object. In
Peirce's metaphysic, the counterpart of the name is the endless thought, the
endless evolution.
Timo Maran
Department of Semiotics
University of Tartu
Tiigi St. 78, 50140 Tartu, Estonia
timo_m@ut.ee
Mimicry-like phenomena has been described both in the evolutionary and individual level of (bio)semiotic systems. Mimicry and crypsis occurring in evolutionary time-scale are usually described as biological phenomena by the terms of Bathesian, Müllerian, aggressive mimicry and others. Whereas deceptive behaviour arising from activity of the individuals is often regarded belonging to the sphere of human culture. In this paper attempt is made to consider both mimicry (evolutionary level) and mimesis (individual level) as two possible semiotic deceptive systems or as the two different ways of functioning these systems. Comparing mimicry and mimesis schematically shows characteristic features of both.
Through the actual cases it is shown, that both mimicry and mimesis cross the culture-nature borderline although the first is definitely more common in biological sphere whereas the other is more concentrated in cultural sphere. Common to the both systems, mimicry and mimeses increase complexity of the semiosphere via cyclical communication and selective feedback — the trait that may consider as the common feature to the all mimicry-like systems.
References
Maran, Timo 1999. A note on
the semiotics of biological mimicry. Sign
Systems Studies 27: 139–146.
— 2001. Mimicry: Towards a
semiotic understanding of nature. Sign
Systems Studies 29(1): 325–339.
Anton Markoš,
Fatima Cvrčková
Faculty of Sciences,
Charles University Prague,
Viničná 7, Praha 2, Czechia 128 00
markos@cts.cuni.cz
The prevailing contemporary view of organic life, coined largely by the
classics of molecular biology and the new evolutionary synthesis, is based on
the assumption that structural and functional features of organisms are fully
encoded in their DNA genomes. Development is therefore understood as execution
of the genetic program for construction of a given species of organism (Davidson 2001).
Such a metaphor leads to questions regarding the nature of the hardware,
operation system and programming language responsible for execution of the
program. We can safely ignore such questions only under assumption that the
non-program components remain constant throughout evolution and ontogeny.
However, there is abundant evidence that this “wetware” is species-specific or
context-dependent. The same DNA sequence (“genetic text”) can, however, be
interpreted in a context-dependent manner, as documented, e.g., by:
·
“misinterpretations”
of cloned genes in different organisms (leading to improper spatial folding of
encoded protein or even to improper delimitation of protein-coding message);
·
epigenetic
memory — heritable conditions encoded by media other than the sequence of DNA;
·
the
“reaction norm” phenomena, where an established wetware explores the phenotype
phase space, including rarely visited or hidden areas;
·
occurrence
of novel phenotypes in interspecies hybrids, revealing the potential of
alternative interpretations of existing genetic programs;
·
the
action exerted by the expression of homologous (often even identical) genes in
ontogeny (homeotic genes etc.).
Many of such phenomena may become easier to grasp when we abandon the
computer metaphor with its software–hardware (or program–wetware) controversy.
Instead, we suggest a natural-language-based (hermeneutic) framework in which
such phenomena become expected rather than anomalous. A string of digital
symbols cannot contain the rules for its translation into shapes (bodies). The
“being-a-program” is not the property of the string — it must be imposed
(negotiated) from outside, i.e. by the body itself. The metaphor of hard-wired
epigenetic rules that decode messages into bodies can survive only in a
creationist (or, at least, deist) framework. Moreover, even the most engaged
proponents of such worldviews are not entirely consistent in this respect (see,
e.g., the concept of gratuity, Monod 1979).
We propose
that the decision what strings will serve as programs, and how they will be
executed, is made in a process analogous to reading and understanding in a
natural language (Markoš 2002). From such an angle,
individuals, species, and consortia of organisms (bacterial films, symbioses,
host-parasite relationships, etc.) become analogies of culture, with their
“wetware” rules molded by contingencies of their evolutionary history.
References
Davidson, E. H. 2001. Genomic
regulatory systems. Development and evolution. Academic Press.
Monod, J. 1979. Chance and
necessity. Collins/Fount.
Markoš, A. 2002. Readers of
the book of life. Contextualizing evolutionary developmental biology.
Oxford UP.
Hiroyuki Matsumoto
Department of
Biochemistry and Molecular Biology
University of Oklahoma Health Sciences Center
Oklahoma City, Oklahoma 73190, U.S.A.
hiro-matsumoto@ouhsc.edu
The draft of the human genome announced in February 2001 marked an epoch in the history of molecular biosciences and will influence the emphasis and direction of biomedical research in the future. With a known genome an entirely new approach is possible for the understanding of life in molecular terms. For example, with the genome information and the data created from the proteins displayed on a two-dimensional gel followed by mass spectrometry, it is now possible to identify the proteins of interest without any presumptions about their identity. Such technique is often called a proteomics approach. A proteomic investigation begins with the discovery of unidentified proteins of interest under well-defined physiological conditions. The operation involves (1) protein display by two-dimensional gel electrophoresis or other separation technique, (2) determination of protein entities, (3) peptide mass fingerprinting, and (4) genome/proteome database search. We show that the methodology of the proteomics approach is characterized neither by deduction nor by induction in the traditional sense, but is a clear example of what C. S. Peirce described as abductive inference almost a century ago. The investigation of complex signaling pathways is intractable to deductive and inductive methods due to its extreme complexity. We show two cases of the proteomics approach as applied to the visual systems of the fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster, and rodents. These examples illustrate the role of abductive inference in proteomics, a discipline at the forefront of current studies in molecular biology.
Christophe
Menant
crmenant@free.fr
Abstract. Biosemiotics and Semiotics have similarities and
differences. Both deal with signal and meaning. One difference is that
Biosemiotics covers a domain (life) that is less complex than the one addressed
by Semiotics (human). We believe that this difference can be used to have
Biosemiotics bringing added value to Semiotics. This belief is based on the
fact that a theory of meaning is easier to build up for living elements than
for human, and that the results obtained for life can make available some tolls
usable for a higher level of complexity.
Semiotic has been encountering some difficulties to
deliver a scientific theory of meaning that can be efficient at the level of
human mind. The obstacles making difficult such theory of meaning can be
understood as resulting of our ignorance on the nature of human. As it is true
that we do not understand the nature of human mind on a scientific basis.
On the other hand, the
nature and properties of life are better understood. And we can propose a
modelization for a generation of meaningful information in the field of
elementary life. Once such modelization established, it is possible to look at
how it could be extended to the domain of human life.
Such an approach on a theory of meaning, beginning in
Biosemiotics and aiming at Semiotics, is what we present in this paper. Taking
an elementary living element as reference, we introduce the bases of a systemic
theory of meaning. Using a simple living system submitted to a constraint, we
define a meaningful information, a meaning generator system and some elements
related to meaningful information transmission. We then try to identify the
hypothesis that need to be taken into account in order to look at extending to
human the results obtained for living elements.
Semiotics
and biosemiotics. Information and meaning
Semiotics
and Biosemiotics entertain multiple and complex relations. Several definitions
are available for these two words [1; 2], but there is a characteristic we
would like to underline. It is about the domains covered. Semiotics address
information and meaning for human. Biosemiotics address information and meaning
for non human living elements.
In
terms of evolution, the Biosemiotics domain appeared on earth billions of years
before the Semiotics domain. On an evolutionary stand point, Semiotics is
rooted in Biosemiotics. So Semiotics can be looked at as a branch of
Biosemiotics, as human is a branch of animal life. And this parallel is
interesting because of the difficulties encountered in the understanding of the
nature of human. Indeed, the nature of human is today out of reach of
scientific knowledge. Despite the efforts of philosophy, psychology,
anthropology and neurosciences, the nature of human mind is currently unknown
(the "hard problem").
On
the contrary, the nature of life is rather well understood on a scientific
basis. And, as Semiotics is a result of Biosemiotics evolution, we want to
believe that modelizing some functions in the field of Biosemiotics will
provide models that could find interesting application in the field of
Semiotics. In other words, evolution from Biosemiotics to Semiotics can be an
interesting window on the transition from animal to man.
Biosemiotics
and Semiotics cover many parameters. And we need to make a choice in order to
work on a practical example. The concept of meaning is a good choice, as it is
of some interest for both fields [3].
We
are going to build up a modelization of meaningful information generation for
Biosemiotics. More precisely, we will analyze meaningful information generation
for simple living elements in order to make available a model that could shed
some light on the understanding of meaningful information generation for human
(Semiotics).
A
theory of meaning for biosemiotics
Looking
for a simple living element that is well known, we can choose the Paramecium.
Many
behaviors of paramecia have been studied, and some can be looked as displaying
the existence of meaningful information generation.
Take for instance a paramecium living in water, and assume that the water
becomes acid in the vicinity of the little animal. The paramecium will rapidly
move away towards a less acid area. It seems quite obvious that the presence of
acid has participated to the build up of some meaningful information in the
paramecium. Meaningful information sounding like: "the environment is
becoming incompatible with survival". And the paramecium to react
correspondingly by moving away from the acid location.
Basically,
three elements have participated to the creation of this meaningful information
within the paramecium:
— the constraint of staying alive;
— the acid water becoming close;
— the incompatibility between the satisfaction of the constraint and the acid
water.
This
example of a paramecium building up "meaning" from the presence of
acid water can be represented as a system (Fig 1), the meaningful information
being the connection existing between the constraint of the system (to stay
alive) and the received information (acid in water).
The
meaningful information (acid non compatible with staying alive) will be used by
the system to participate to the determination of an action aimed at the
satisfaction of the constraints (move away from acid area).
Such
a modelization brings up the definition on a meaningful information, with
corresponding properties:
"A
meaning is a meaningful information that is created by a system submitted to a
constraint when it receives an external information that has a connection with
the constraint. The meaning is formed of the connection existing between the
incident information and the constraint of the system. The function of the
meaningful information is to participate to the determination of an action that
will be implemented in order to satisfy the constraint of the system".
(Properties
of a meaningful information are detailed at I.1 in [4].)
Towards
a theory of meaning for semiotics
The
generation of a meaning in a simple living element as introduced here above can
be generalized into a Meaning Generator System (MGS) built up with the
following elements:
— a system submitted to a constraint and able to receive an incident
information;
— an information incident on the system;
— an information processing element, internal to the system and capable of
identifying a connection between the received information and the constraint.
An
MGS is represented in Fig 2 where a system submitted to a constraint S
generates a meaningful (S) information that will be used to satisfy the
constraint of the system.
It
is to be noted that the meaningful (S) information created by a system S can
exist for some usage internal to S, but can also be transmitted for usage by
other systems.
Let's assume that the system (S) generates and sends out a meaningful (S)
information, and that this information is received by another system (S')
submitted to the constraint (S'). What will be the effect of the meaningful (S)
information in he system (S') ?
In order to address this question, we need to define the "domain of
efficiency (S) of a meaning" as being the domain where the meaningful (S)
information is capable to participate to the determination of an action aimed
at satisfying the constraint S.
We state that the meaningful (S) information is efficient (S) in the domain of
efficiency (S).
These elements bring us to define and analyse different cases where an
information can be meaningful (S) and efficient (S) or not, depending upon the
location of the signal carrying the information vs the constraints S.
(These cases are analysed at I.3 in [4].)
Meaningful
information processing in a living element (Biosemiotics) has allowed us to
build an MGS. Next step is to see how this MGS can be used to shed some light
in meaningful information processing in human (Semiotics).
This subject being currently under analysis. We will only present here some
first directions of investigation.
First,
our hypothesis that the MGS is a general system and that the proposed
modelization can remain valid for complex systems, assuming we locate the
complexity within the elements that constitute the system, and assuming that
several systems can work together (we keep in mind that this hypothesis has to
be validated).
Then,
regarding the case of human, we consider that at least two interacting MGSs
have to be taken into account.
— The MGS applied to the living aspect of human where the constraints will be
the ones existing for all living elements (vital constraints: survival and
reproduction).
— The MGS applied to the psychic aspect of human where the constraints are the
ones made available by psychology and psychoanalytic theory (combine pleasure
and reality, valorization of the ego, combine impulses of life and death,
limitation of anxiety...).
Much work is to be done in this last field, looking at the new constraint as
they could have appeared during evolution from animal to human.
Even
if the understanding of these new constraints deserves significant effort, it
is possible to propose today a simplified draft of MGS for human (taking into
account the two intricated MGSs with the set of corresponding constraints). Fig
3 illustrates this very preliminary version.
Conclusion
We
have tried in this short paper to show how a modelization in the field of
Biosemiotics could provide a tool having possible usage for studies in
Semiotics.
With
an example of meaningful information generation in a simple living element, we
have built up a model of a Meaning Generator System (MGS) that can find some
application in the field of meaningful information generation in human. Work is
still to be done in this last area, but the proposed MGS is an example of
Biosemiotics added value to Semiotics.
References
[1] Sharov, A. What is
biosemiotics? http://www.zbi.ee/~uexkull/biosem.htm
[2] http://www.indiana.edu/~educp550/define.html
[3] Emmeche, Claus
2002. The chicken and the Orphean egg: On the function of meaning and the
meaning of function. Sign Systems Studies 30(1): 15–32.
[4] Menant, C. http://www.theory-meaning.fr.st/
Tiberiu G. Mustata
Institute of Pathology, Case Western Reserve University
Cleveland, Ohio, USA
gtmustat@yahoo.com
The term semiotic is instrumentally
understood here as an approach opposed to mechanicism in the field of medicine
and medical anthropology. We identify three semiotically relevant matters in
the homeopathic setting.
First, homeopathy never
deals with common pathophysiological reasoning but only with symptomatology.
The aim is not to decipher and subsequently recover an altered mechanism but to
reconstitute a typology by its constellation of signs. Furthermore homeopathy
treats the disease by handling the relation between the signs and the governor
principle of their dynamic, i.e. the similar remedy. This commitment is
reflected by the homeopathic main principle: Similia similibus currentur.
Secondly, in the homeopathic
respect, disease is not a material phenomenon occurring at the level of
physical body and having emotional and mental consequences. It is rather a
subtle phenomenon which reflects itself physically, mentally and emotionally
when disturbed. Even that these three modes of being are hierarchically
assembled from the standpoint of their causal power the real ground of disease
stands beyond them. The acting principle which grounds the three-tiered realm
of manifestation was historically called the vital force. However, the semiotic
heritage allows us to treat it in the terms of Thirdness and to set a deeper
interpretation of vitalism.
Finally, the relation among
the individual being (a patient), the remedy and the vital force while
beautifully depicting a triad enlarges the frame of understanding beyond the
biological, psychological and chemical realms. Science cannot explain
satisfactorily how a substance while loosing its materiality through the
process of dilution and potentation gains tremendous powers upon the being.
According to us, the answer should be sought in the semiotic nature of reality:
what is manifested represents only a sign of the non-manifested object.
Homeopathy is a royal way in understanding the depth of semiotic approach this
respect because it enlightens semiosis not only in the horizontal relations among
the levels of manifestation but also explores the vertical relations between
them and their governing principle.
Toshiyuki Nakajima
Department of Biology & Earth Sciences
Ehime University
2-5 Bunkyo-cho, Matsuyama, Ehime790-8577, Japan
nakajima@sci.ehime-u.ac.jp
Biological adaptation to the environment involves continual maintenance of a particular set of relationships with the environment at relatively higher probabilities than expected in abiotic processes. Molecules involved in living systems, cells, and organisms discriminate between environmental configurations, and act selectively to establish a particular relation with the environment. Probabilities of events occurring to actors are determined by the degree of discriminability and selectivity in action or cognition, where the probability of an event is defined as the degree of certainty at which it occurs among events possibly occurring to a focal actor. In other words, they can control the probabilities of events occurring to themselves through discriminative and selective actions. What is discriminated by an actor constitutes its umwelt. In this sense, the construction of umwelt and the ability of controlling probabilities of events are closely interrelated. The problem addressed in this paper is to formalize this interrelation. Interactions between a focal biological actor (e.g. molecule, cell, organism) and the environment can be represented as sign processing between the actor and the environment. An actor in a general sense, called cognizer, acts against a given environmental state, while the environment acts against the cognizerB!Gs state, where action implies shifting from one state to another against a given configuration of others, a generalized concept of motion, called cognition. This description of a focal cognizer and its environment is framed by a meta-observer, located outside the world including both of them. Conceptual distinction between the environment for the meta-observer and the umwelt for a focal cognizer is important. The umwelt is constituted by what is discriminated by the cognizer, smaller than the environment described by the meta-observer. Unlike the meta-observer, organisms, molecules and cells as well, are not omnipotent in discriminating between all the differences in the environment under the meta-observer view. They instead construct their own umwelt, smaller than the environment, within which differences are discriminated to raise probabilities of preferable events and reduce the less preferable for maintaining organization or survival.
Stephen Pain
University of East Anglia
England
Etien55@excite.com
st3pen@hotmail.com
In this paper I shall set out my conception and theory of rhetoric, beginning with a historical overview of rhetoric, and shortly follow this with a discussion of contemporary usage of rhetoric, particularly rhetoric/s of biology. I intend to distinguish the deconstruction of rhetoric from my own approach. I will discuss the definition of “life” and rhetoric and proceed with a formalisation of rhetoric, setting out the key components of rhetoric, the nature of argument and probability, enthymetic reasoning, rhetorical agency (rhetor and audience), rhetorical situation, rhetorical competency and epistemic determinancy. I will also discuss symbolic rhetoric, the development of constructive species specific rhetoric in connection with Uexküll’s theory of significance, and round up by summarising the possible applications with a series of case studies.
Mark Reybrouck
Section of
Musicology
Catholic University of Leuven
Blijde-Inkomststraat 21, Leuven, Belgia
Mark.Reybrouck@arts.kuleuven.ac.be
This paper is programmatic in its claims. It questions the biological bases of musical epistemology and stresses the role of ecological constraints in knowledge construction as applied to music. It takes as a starting point the biosemiotical approach to perception, which encompasses the whole domain from lower sensory functioning to higher levels of cognitive processing. Central in this approach is the possibility to interact with the sonic environment and to modify the semantic relations with the world. As such the listener can be conceived as an ‘adaptive device’ which can expand its perceptual, motor and conceptual tools in an attempt to make sense out of the outer world. In order to make these claims operational we propose to lean upon the concepts of circularity of stimulus and reaction (Uexküll, Piaget), the experiential or enactive approach to cognition (Varela, Johnson, Lakoff) and the concepts of semantic closure and epistemic autonomy. Listening, then, is a kind of ‘coping behaviour’ which fits the sollicitations of the sonic environment. For doing so, the listener can rely on his wired-in machinery, but it is possible to transcend this stimulus-bound reactivity as well. This involves a shift from conservative to anticipatory behaviour, which goes beyond the closed-loop character of sensorimotor integration. The brain, then, acts not merely as a controller, but as a simulator, which performs internal computations on the observables. A major problem, however, is the delimitation of the elements on which to do the computations. Our proposal is to start from ‘event perception’, which implies both a ‘bottom-up’ and ‘top-down’ approach to knowledge acquisition. It allows, further, a transition from ecological to symbolic knowledge and offers interesting cognitive tools for doing the conceptualization which calls forth principles of cognitive economy. An attempt is made, finally, to translate this to the realm of music.
References
Reybrouck, M. 2001. Biological roots of musical epistemology: Functional
cycles, umwelt, and enactive listening. Semiotica 134(1/4): 599–633.
Reybrouck, M. 2001. Musical imagery between sensory processing and
ideomotor simulation. In: R. I. Godøy, H. Jörgensen (eds.), Musical Imagery.
Lisse: Swets & Zeitlinger, 117–136.
Torsten Rüting
Universität Hamburg
Institut für Geschichte der Naturwissenschaften,Mathematik und Technik
Bundesstr. 55, D-20146 Hamburg, Germany
rueting@.math.uni-hamburg.de
The “Institut für Umweltforschung” was founded by Jakob von Uexküll 1925 at Hamburg university. After the war this institute was situated in a private house in Hamburg until the sixties. At the dissolving of the institute parts of the library and the files reached the zoological institute of the University of Hamburg and the Federal Archives. The Uexküll family provided the collection of private offprints of Jakob von Uexküll to the Senckenberg library in Frankfurt. These approx. 4200 Separata and 120 monographs were submitted to the zoological institute and museum of the University of Hamburg in 1983. On request of Gösta and Thure von Uexküll a “Jakob von Uexküll-Archiv” should arise there. To this day, the construction of the archive was not perfected. For this reason different representatives of the University of Hamburg were against lending inventory of the “Nachlass” to Tartu University and the Uexküll Center in 1997. The question of the Uexküll-Archive hasn't been followed up since. I now make plans for a project in cooperation with Professor Hünemörder of the Institute for history of science, mathematics and technology of the University of Hamburg, which has good chances to include the partnership between the Universities of Tartu and Hamburg as well as several foundations. A stipend was granted to me by the “Marga and Kurt Möllgaard-Stiftung” in order to go to Tartu and for the Gathering in Biosemiotics. I hope for good cooperation with the Jakob von Uexküll-Centre and the society of the Biosemiotics.
I want to make the restoration of the Jakob von Uexküll-Archive the basis for writing a history of Umweltforschung and biosemiotics. For this greater project I seek suggestions, ideas and hints to interesting questions and subjects.
My own background is a Diploma in Biology
(Neurophysiology) and PhD in History of Science. I was graduated with a
Dissertation on the development and influence of Ivan Pavlov’s research project
in Russia and the Soviet Union.
Sustainability during
development depends on the types of part-whole interactions: Logical comparisons
of biological systems of various structural levels
Alexander E. Sedov
Institute for the History of Science and Technology
Russian Academy of Sciences
Staropansky per. 1/5, 103012 Moscow, Russia
sedov@ihst.ru
Using various examples, i.e. main problems in different branches and levels of modern biology, the concepts of classificational, structural, and functional multilevel clusters and hierarchies are discussed and summarized. Some general system sophistications for all these cases of different levels, that are useful for empirical research, are proposed. So, here are analyzed main cluster approaches in classification, logical variability for bases in structural clusterisation, and variability in semantical values of similar functional elements of different biosystems. The meta-concept ‘heterological transpositions’ that embraces various levels of human-caused biological phenomena, is proposed and summarized in the three-level table. It permits to analyze these phenomena using the strict analogies in comparisons of different levels. The main ideas seem to have high predictive potential for many cases of modern biology, and, moreover, for various social and technical phenomena.
The pedagogical aspects of these approaches for high education, and even for school education, is discussed all along the paper.
Stephen Springette
tramont@iinet.net.au
Pragmatism is the
idea that we learn about our worlds through our bodies. Ipso facto, it
follows that different bodies will be predisposed to learning different kinds
of logics. How might we apprehend the essence of these logics?
I apply Peirce's "law of association of habits", in conjunction with a more general interpretation of Heidegger's "Dasein". Peirce regarded habit and association as fundamental aspects of consciousness. Thus, he proclaimed his "law of association of ideas": "There is a law in this association of ideas. We may roughly say it is the law of habit. It is the great 'Law of association of ideas' - the one law of all psychical action".
I want to be
more specific with the relationship between association and habit, and that is
why I would prefer to refer to his Great Law as the "Law of association of
habits".
In summary, I
apply Peirce's law of association of habits and Heidegger's Dasein to infer
three crucial points about gender roles: (1) Gender roles are habits. Thus, we
can infer that: (2) Gender roles are chosen. And from a more general
interpretation of Heidegger's Dasein (I call it the desire to be) we know that:
(3) Men and women "like" the roles to which they have been assigned.
What is even more exciting about the application of semiotics to understanding
gender roles is the treasure of interpretations we might derive not only for
how men and women relate to each other, but also for how we might infer the
cognitive realms of non-human animals and inter-galactic aliens.
What Heidegger refers to as
"being-in-the-world" (Dasein) is actually closer to my own
definition that I call "the desire to be". The key point here is that
choice molds desire, and that desires are as infinitely moldable as there are
an infinitude of choices that might be made. To put it more simply, we become
what we choose. The choices we make shape what we become. The reason we humans
don't eat dirt is that we do not have the bodies of earthworms. So, while dirt
might be particularly alluring to some critters, to others, it will arouse
considerably less excitement.
References
http://members.iinet.net.au/~tramont/biosem.html
http://members.iinet.net.au/~tramont/applied.html
Frederik Stjernfelt
Department of Comparative Literature, University of Copenhagen
Njalsgade 80A, 2300 Copenhagen, Denmark
stjern@hum.ku.dk
After some decades of biosemiotic research and discussions, the time seems right for establishing and scrutinising the basic hypotheses supported by that research.
Emmeche C., Kull K., Stjernfelt F. 2002. Reading
Hoffmeyer, Rethinking Biology. Tartu: Tartu University Press.
Stjernfelt F. 2002. Tractatus Hoffmeyerensis:
Biosemiotics as expressed in 22 basic hypotheses. Sign Systems Studies
30(1): 337–345.
Richard Strohman
University
of California at Berkeley
Department
of Molecular and Cell Biology
229 Stanley Hall, Berkeley, CA 94720-3206, USA
strohman@uclink4.berkeley.edu
Modern
biology and its codependent biotechnology are undergoing a dual revolution. The
first is illusory and represented by
a triumphant molecular genetics symbolized by the Human Genome Project and the
acknowledged genetic determinist paradigm
of 20th century biology. Relying on another metaphor, genetic programs, it promises to reconstruct the living world from
"the genome up". The second,
real, revolution is all about the
denial of the first. As the reductionist program continues to reveal finer
details of life's complex organization it also reveals "anomalies" or
failure of experimental results to confirm the genetic paradigm driving the
experiments. The genetic paradigm
cannot assimilate these anomalies and so one may conclude that something vital
is missing from it: and this problem deepens with each week of new reports in Nature and Science. Still, the hype for genetic determinism continues and the
technology, ignoring all warnings issuing from anomaly, presses on ...
apparently on the basis of a flawed scientific paradigm ...to transform the
intellectual products of the laboratory into the material products of the
medical and pharmaceutical marketplace. It is at the nexus of these two
revolutions that one may identify first, a powerful source of conflict of
interest between technology and science, and second, a more fundamental
conflict defined by the differences between a world of made and a world of born and the ethical problems inherent
in the conflation of these two worlds.
It is in this context that I would like to have a conversation concerning (a) what is missing from genetics, (b) concerning the complementation of genetics with dynamical systems thinking and (c) concerning the relationship between the genotype and phenotype. Biology today finds itself suspended, not only over the abyss of the genotype-phenotype relationship but over the epistemological abyss of a deterministic-dynamic systems model of life itself. In both of these is the irreducibility of phenotype to genotype, and the possibility, best defined by Howard Pattee and Walter Elsasser, of a new paradigm in which genetics is complemented by biological systems and their dynamical laws. Pattee has discussed this in terms of the complementation of semiotics with dynamics. I will bring to the conference a stunning ignorance of semiotics but also an up-to-date report on the emergence of dynamical processes as a major new feature in experimental biology. These processes include self-organizing metabolic pathways governed by the known laws of chemistry (kinetics & thermodynamics), and by epigenetic genome-marking systems that pose a new question: ”What is the context-dependent phenotype of the genotype?” Laws governing the construction and function of epigenetic self-organizing systems remain completely unknown. These epigenetic systems interpret the world without for the world within and, in that activity, define (give meaning to?) the sequences in DNA. I agree with E. F. Keller: in eukaryotic organisms there are no genes until they emerge as the products of dynamic systems operations refined by natural selection on the basis of their functional usefulness.
Gottfried Suessenbacher
Department of Psychological Basic Research
Institute of Psychology, University of Klagenfurt
Austria
Gottfried.Suessenbacher@uni-klu.ac.at
When trying to explain the enigmatic beginning of mankind many authors interested in the evolution of human culture investigated the correlations between factors such as encephalization, toolmaking capabilities, dieting habits, communicative skills etc. Alas, despite the relevance of the usage of fire — being the differentia specifica (Blumenberg, 1979) — only in passing did they refer to the competence in methods of fire usage in this respect. Arguments relating to this question have, on one hand, addressed the change of diet and other multifarious advantages of the use of fire; on the other hand, it seemed self-evident that Early homo developed the competence of using fire because their intelligence was improved by the successful experience of tool-using techniques, predesigned by the evolution of hand-brain-interaction, and supported by early communicative skills.
Applying the question of how the early Homo developed the capacitiy to deal with fire to the question of whether mythology offers some hints in this respect one can find two complexes of creative fantasy within Greek mythology — Dionysos and Prometheus (and numerous other stories from different cultures). Philosophy has dealt with these protagonists extensively (e.g. Nietzsche, Blumenberg); however, so far, nobody has related their thoughts to a hypothesis of Evolutionary Psychology (cf. Buss 1999) where many critics identify a lack of inspiration.
In order to offer new incentives for research undertaken by Evolutionary Psychology this paper connects modular hypotheses about the origin of fluid/hybrid intelligence (cf. Mithen 1996; Donald 2001) to semiotic hypotheses (cf. Deacon 1997). It analyzes in detail the necessary steps, which had to occur in order to eventually not only maintain but also create fire — steps which, of course, correspond with successive stages in the human evolution proposed by evolutionary theorists. However, inherent in these stages were transitions which led from a status of early homo living in a world represented by iconic and indexical reference processes to a status where first-person contents of thought should not only imply the concept “I” but also be free for both iconic as well as symbolic thought and communication. These transitions can be best be explained by considering the necessary cognitive as well as emotional and communicative steps which had to occur in order for fire to eventually be used in the way our species uses it.
The myth of Prometheus indicates the beginning and the step-by-step improvement of ritualistic group behavior regulating fire use, which on one hand led to the recognition of the interplay of fire with other “elements” (in this way developing cognitive abilities), on the other hand helped them to cope with contradictions between instincts and emotions (e. g., horror vs. desire). The myth of Dionysos, however, indicates changes of sexuality regarding social as well as physical conditions. Both myths, nevertheless, relate to experiences of sacrilege and punishment — experiences which can be exploited to some advantage: The hypothetical steps of mastering fire implicate achievements of mimetical coordination as well as affective disciplination the struggles of which can best be described by using these myths as starting-points of evolutionary research.
Edwina Taborsky
Bishop’s University, 39 Jarvis St. #318, Toronto, Ontario,
Canada M5E 1Z5
taborsky@primus.ca
This paper
examines our cosmos as an ongoing thermodynamics of both conservation of
mass/information and conservation of energy. This is a pansemiotic rather than
a biosemiotic architecture and endeavours to explore abiotic and biotic mass as
semiosic transformations of ‘uninformed to informed mass’ within different realms
of semiosic organization.
To explain this perspective,
the paper investigates the semiosic process within a dynamic model.
First, it differentiates this model from the “primitive model”. The
primitive model operates within a framework where its parts and wholes function
within one mode of reality, that of “rest-mass” in current time. This is the
domain of our familiar experiences. The framework is ontologically dyadic and
examines information and knowledge as formal descriptions of these objective or
external entities of “rest-mass”. The model establishes a mechanical
descriptive action, operating in absolute time, where one side of the dyad
“represents” the material other side by a particular and/or aggregate
descriptive classification, which is held by a mediator agent, the interpreter.
The dynamic model functions within three modes of reality. It adds to the
external rest-mass a rich internal process, with three internal processes that
set up mass as an ongoing dynamics of relations. These internal motions obscure
the rest-mass membranes of the external entities as well as the formal
representational descriptions. The resultant entanglement of the internal with
the external moves mass/information from its isolation as an inert rest-mass to
the transformative dissipative and ampliative openness of “relational mass”. To
maintain this dynamic state of a “constrained evolving exploration” of ongoing
intransitive relations; that is, a world of infinite inexhaustible
transformations of mass to information, we postulate, in the second part of the
paper, the existence in this triadic architecture of a complex hierarchy of
temporal modes, involving five levels of entangled time processes. The paper
examines the role of time in the generation of knowledge and information and
presents a model of mass/energy as a dynamic force involved in a constant
transformative exploration of its own nature. Third, the paper examines these
transformative explorations as operations that take place in three separate
codal realms, the abiotic, biotic and conceptual realms, and examines the
nature of semiosic codification within each realm.
Morten Tønnessen
Department of Philosophy
University of Oslo
mortentonnessen@hotmail.com
Has the Umwelt theory got any ethical implications, or affinities? Can a study of Uexküll’s principles contribute to ethics? In search for an Umwelt ethics, I will start by analysing Uexküll’s biologism, which is obvious, e. g., in his Staatsbiologie, and his justification of pain by reference to the “Plan des Organismus” (Uexküll 1928: 131). While Jesper Hoffmeyer (1993) argues that a biosemiotic approach favours one particular ethical system, I will argue that the Umwelt theory could be regarded as consistent with several ethical systems, gradualistic and egalitarian alike. In this connection, topics such as biodiversity, cultural diversity and animal welfare will be addressed. Finally, I will suggest that the Umwelt theory can provide environmental ethics with a fruitful re-definition of what it means to be a sensing being: Namely, an Umwelt-owner, that is, a subject of the phenomenal world.
References
Hoffmeyer, Jesper 1993.
Biosemiotics and ethics. In: Witoszek, Nina; Gulbrandsen, Elizabeth (eds.), Culture
and Environment: Interdisciplinary Approaches. Oslo: Center for Development
and the Environment, 152–176.
Kull, Kalevi 2001.
Biosemiotics and the problem of intrinsic value of nature. Sign Systems
Studies 29(1): 353–365.
Tønnessen, Morten 2001. Outline of an Uexküllian bio-ontology. Sign Systems Studies 29(2): 683–692.
Uexküll, Jakob von 1928. Theoretische Biologie. Berlin: Verlag
von Julius Springer.
Aleksei Turovski
Tallinn Zoo,
Tallinn, Estonia
p.turovski@tallinnlv.ee
References
Turovski A. 2000. The semiotics of animal freedom: A
zoologist’s attempt to perceive the semiotic aim of H. Hediger. Sign Systems Studies 28: 380–386.
— 2001. On the parasite’s association as a
vectorizing factor in biosemiotic development. Semiotica 134(1/4): 409–414.
— 2002. On the zoosemiotics of health and disease. Sign
Systems Studies 30(1): 213–219.
Tommi
Vehkavaara
Department of Mathematics, Statistics, and Philosophy
University of Tampere
Finland
tommi.vehkavaara@uta.fi
I will continue on what I ended in the first Gatherings and give a
proposal for what could be the result of the naturalization of semiotic
concepts in a sense of semiotic naturalism (cf. Vehkavaara 2002). The approach
is restricted to agential semiosis, but the concept of agent is considered as
general concept as I can see possible.
I will
propose that the concept of representation should be ‘overgeneralized’ beyond
genuine semiotic processes. The prototype of the most primitive concept of
representation can be found in any goal-directed control system like
thermostats. This corresponds to representation at level 4 in Mark Bickhard’s
theory of interactive representation (Bickhard 1998). The interaction of the
subsystem (measuring device) of a thermostat with its environment indicates
different activities (heating or not heating) depending on the quality of the
environment (the temperature). A thermostat makes the environmental
representation and uses it when it is functioning to fulfill its goal (to keep
steady temperature etc.). At this level, there is not yet any object of representation
for the system. When a system starts to maintain a set of ‘default-settings’
for its activities (at levels 6 and 7 in Bickhard’s theory), it becomes capable
to ‘observe objects’ and to create its Umwelt. At this level most
Peircean and Uexküllian semiotic concepts become applicable.
The
goal-relative validity of the primitive representation is independent on the
origin of the system. The historicity of a representative system is
nevertheless needed in order to understand the nature of the goals. Thermostats
and other machines are mere quasi-agents, because their goals are not ‘their
own’ but human ones — they are made to fulfill human purposes. Any goal of any
control system is either ‘other-organized’, i.e. set by some other quasi-agent
when it is trying to achieve its goals (e.g. parasite-host relation), or
self-organized. Self-organization of goals is possible at least in systems that
are far from thermodynamical equilibrium. The most primitive goal is a
self-maintenance of a far-from-equilibrium system. This goal is significant for
the system itself, because it is its existential condition — if a system fails
to achieve this goal, the system dies. It is hypothesized that any apparent
real goal, intention, purpose, etc. of a system is embodied as some subsystem
that is maintaining itself far-from-equilibrium. The minimal criterion for the concept
of semiotic agent could then be that an agent must be a representative system
(control system) with at least one goal of its own. Consequently, a genuine
agent is ‘potentially immortal’ self-maintaining far-from-equilibrium system
that is potentially capable changing its goals in interaction with its environment.
One benefit
of separating the concept of representation and its validity from the evolution
and nature of goals is that these rather formal concepts are applicable in
biosemiotics as well as in robosemiotics.
Bickhard, Mark H. 1998. Levels of representationality. Journal of
Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence 10(2):
179–215.
Bickhard, Mark H. with Campbell, Donald T. 2000. Emergence. In: Andersen, Peter Bøgh; Emmeche,
Claus; Finnemann, Niels Ole; Christiansen, Peder Voetmann (eds.), Downward
Causation: Minds, Bodies, and Matter. Århus: Aarhus University Press,
322–348.
Peirce, Charles S. 1931–1935, 1958. Collected papers of C. S. Peirce.
Vols. 1–6 (Hartshorne, Charles; Weiss, Paul, eds.); vols. 7–8 (Burks, Arthur
W., ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. [Cited as CP.]
— 1992,
1998. Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings. Vols. 1–2. (Hauser, Nathan et al., ed.) Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
[Cited as EP.]
Vehkavaara, Tommi 2002. Why
and how to naturalize semiotic concepts for biosemiotics. Sign Systems
Studies 30(1): 293–313.
Mark Vian
Stream Management Program, NYCDEP
USA
VianM@water.dep.nyc.ny.us
The current species extinction event
is generally understood as being caused by human behaviors that continue to
undermine the functioning of ecosystems (Wilson 1992; Hilton-Taylor 2000).
While ecosystem function has traditionally been described in terms of the
structure and flux of organisms, materials and energy, the ecosemiotic
viewpoint understands these ecosystem structures and fluxes as largely mediated
by fluxes of meaning, and interprets the rapid ecosystem degradation (and
comcomittant species extinctions) as the result of the inadequate coupling of
human and non-human semiotic systems (Zucker et al. 2001, in press).
This paper explores several strategies to create a coupling that will terminate
the functional cycles (Uexküll 1932) of unsustainable human behaviors.
The first section of the paper presents an ecosemiotic
analysis of the development of the notion of “biotic integrity” in the United
States. I employ Latour’s (1999) idea of “circulating reference” to describe
the sequence of articulations in the evolution of “biotic integrity”: from a
concept inherent in a legalistic semiotic (Clean Water Act 1977), to a term of
scientific discourse (Karr 1981), which attempts to embody the zoosemiotic of
freshwater fish communities, as a surrogate indicator of a broader ecosemiotic
of “ecosystem health”, brought back
into the legalistic discourse to effect regulatory actions, ultimately to
coerce changes in public behavior and terminate a variety of (dysfunctional)
functional cycles. The notion of using, in this strategy, “reference
conditions” that exhibit characteristics “comparable to the best situations
without the influence of man” (Karr 1981) is discussed as both a technical and
philosophical problematic.
The second section of the paper speculates on a complementary strategy for coupling human and non-human semiotics to produce feedback mechanisms that reduce environmentally damaging human behavior. This experimental strategy is characterized by methods that, rather than simply articulating more elements of environmental semiosis into the human Umwelt, alter the perceived boundary between Self and Other within the Umwelt.
References
Hilton-Taylor, C. (ed.)
2000. 2000 IUCN Red List of Threatened Species. IUCN/SSC, Gland,
Switzerland and Cambridge, UK.
Karr, J. R. 1981. Assessment of biotic integrity using fish
communities. Fisheries 6(6): 21–27.
Latour, B. 1999. Pandora’s
Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Boston: Harvard University
Press.
Uexküll, J. 1992 [1934]. A stroll
through the worlds of animals and men: A picture book of invisible worlds. As
republished in Semiotica 89(4).
Wilson, E. O. 1992. The
Diversity of Life. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.
Zucker, L.A., Weekes, A.,
Vian, M.A. and Dorsey, J. 2001. Treating Rivers as Systems to Meet Multiple
Objectives. In: France, Robert (ed.), Handbook of Water Sensitive Planning
and Design. CRC/Lewis Publ.
Andreas Weber
Institute for Cultural Studies, Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin
Sophienstraße 22a, D–10178 Berlin, Germany
andreas.weber@rz.hu-berlin.de
The late Chile born biologist Francisco J. Varela has been influential in theoretical biology throughout the last three decades of the 20. century. His thinking shows a marked development from a biologically founded constructivism (developed together with his fellow citizen, Humberto Maturana, with the main key word being “autopoiesis theory”) to a more phenomenological oriented standpoint, which Varela called himself the philosophy of embodiment, or “enactivism”. In this paper I want to show that major arguments in this latter position can be made fruitful for a biosemiotic approach to organism. Varela himself already applies concepts as e.g. “signification”, “relevance”, “meaning” which are de facto biosemiotic. He derives these concepts from a compact theory of organism which he understands as the process of self-realization of a materially embodied subject. This theory is developed, though modified, from Autopoiesis theory and so attempts a quasi-empirical description of the living in terms of self-organization. Varela’s thinking hence might count as an exemplary model for a foundation of a biosemiotic approach in a theory of organism. It can be said with some justification, that Francisco Varela’s thinking offers genuine clues for the broader project of a semiotic biology. Especially Varela’s association with down-to-earth biological research offers tools to link biosemiotics into the ongoing debate about the status of a biological system within genetics and proteomics research.
Tom Ziemke
Department of Computer Science
University of Skovde
Sweden
tom@ida.his.se
Gibson’s affordance concept and von Uexküll's concept of functional tone (as well as Merkwelt/Umwelt) agree in viewing perception as ecologically embedded and arising from the interaction between agents and their environments. They do, however, disagree in the sense that, roughly speaking, Gibson viewed affordances as part of the external environment whereas von Uexküll described functional tones, and their dynamical variation, as part of the subject's inner world. This talk discusses the similarities and differences between the concepts and the underlying theoretical frameworks, and presents simple robotic models of functional tone through varying sensorimotor mappings realized in so-called recurrent neural networks.
Gatherings in Biosemiotics 2
University History Museum
(Toome Hill)
11.00 Registration
desk opened
12.00 Opening,
forewords
M.Anderson,
M.Lotman, C.Emmeche, K.Kull
12.40 Jesper Hoffmeyer
– Scitoi mesoib - or why the genome is so small
13.10 Coffee
break
13.30 Marcello
Barbieri – Organic codes: metaphors or realities?
14.15 Anton Markoš & Fatima Cvrčková – Who is the addressee of the genetic text
15.00 Lunch
16.00 Stefan Artmann
– Four principles of Jacobian biopragmatic
16.30 Stephen
Pain – Introduction to biorhetorics: applied rhetoric in the life
sciences
17.00 Coffee break
17.15 Frederik Stjernfelt – The core hypotheses of
biosemiotics
17.45 Kalevi Kull – Biosemiosis: A search for
other
18.15 Discussion:
Organic codes and first principles of biosemiotics
20.30 Garden party: Karl Ernst von
Baer House (Veski Str. 4)
9.00 Wolfgang Hofkirchner – The differentia
specifica of biosemiosis in the perspective of a theory of evolutionary
systems
9.30 Yagmur Denizhan & Candas Sert
– In search of a reconciliation between semiotics, thermodynamics and
metasystem transition theory
10.00 John Collier – Information expression
requires cohesive levels
10.30 Coffee break
11.00 Claus Emmeche – Biosemiotics and
experiential biology
11.30 Tom Ziemke – Affordance vs. functional
tone: a comparison of Gibson's and von Uexküll's theories
12.00 Coffee break
12.30 Donald Favareau – Collapsing the wave
function of meaning: the contextualizing resources of talk-in-interaction
13.00 Toshiyuki Nakajima – Construction of
umwelt to control probabilities of events in living
13.45 Lunch
15.00 Tommi Vehkavaara – An outline of basic
semiotic concepts for bio- and robosemiotics and the emergence of umwelt
15.30 Mark Reybrouck – A biosemiotic approach to
music cognition: event perception between auditory listening and cognitive
economy
16.00 Coffee break
16.15 Andres Luure – The role of relations in
semiotics
16.45 Sergey Chebanov – Bilateral
biosemiotics: a problem of sense on a super-triplet level
17.15 Coffee break
17.30 Elisabeth Johansson – Biosemiotic
perspectives in gasflux models
18.00 Christophe Menant – From biosemiotics to
semiotics
18.30 Discussion: Formalisation in biosemiotics
20.30 Evening snacks and drinks
(Tammekuru Str. 5)
9.00 Edwina Taborsky – A pansemiotic
architecture
9.30 Soren Brier – Biosemiotics and the
Third Culture
10.00 Coffee break
10.15 Luis Bruni – The global phenotype
10.45 Alexander Sedov – Sustainability during
development depends on the types of part-whole interactions: logical
comparisons of biological systems of various structural levels
11.15 Coffee break
11.30 Myrdene Anderson – Neoteny and its role
in taming and domestication
12.00 Mette Böll – The evolution of empathy in
social systems
12.30 Coffee break
12.45 Domonique Lestel – On the expression of
negation among animals
13.15 Gottfried Suessenbacher – Mythology and
evolutionary psychology: on the relevance of prehistoric fire usage for the
evolution of human culture, consciousness and language
14.00 Lunch
15.00 Aleksei Turovski – The signs of
bizarre characteristics in the semiometabolism of animal associations
15.30 Timo Maran – Mimicry and mimesis in the
bio-semiosphere
16.00 Coffee break
16.15 Mark Vian – Biotic integrity,
ecosemiotic archetypes, and the boundary of self: Some thoughts on the
intentional coupling of human and non-human semiotics
16.45 Morten Tønnessen – Umwelt ethics
17.15 Coffee break
17.30 Tiberiu G. Mustata – The semiotic
substance of homeopathy
18.00 General discussion: Experimental use of
biosemiotics
20.30 Evening tea (Tammekuru
Str. 5)
7.30 Departure to Puhtu
11.00 Arrival to Puhtu, coffee
11.40 K. Kull – Genius loci
12.00 Sune Frølund – Teleology and the
‘natural history of signification’: the implications of Hans Jonas’ bioontology
for biosemiotics
12.30 Torsten Rüting – A project to establish the
Jakob-von-Uexküll-Archiv at the University of Hamburg
13.00 Ester Võsu – How to stage nature
14.00 Lunch in Puhtu
15.00 Laelatu walk
16.00 Departure to Tallinn
18.00 Arrival to Hotel Mihkli in Tallinn
19.30 Dinner in Tallinn Zoo
20.30 Aleksei Turovski – The zoo
as a field of reestablishing semiotic boundaries
22.30 Closing event
24.00 Finish
Departure
from Tallinn
——————